I S K O

edited by Birger Hjørland and Claudio Gnoli

 

Folk classification

Preliminary editorial placeholder article; to be replaced when an author is found for an improved article

Table of contents:
1. Introduction: Definition and synonyms
2. Interdisciplinary research on folk classification
3. Relations between scholarly classification and folk classification
4. Cultural relativist versus cultural universalist views
5. Conclusion: The relevance of folk classification for the KO community
6. Addendum June 2023
Endnotes
References
Colophon

[top of entry]

1. Introduction: Definition and synonyms

Folk classification (or folk taxonomy) is → classification by ordinary people (as opposed to classification by scientists, scholars, and professionals). It may be the classification of plants and animals (as studied in ethnobiology, which is the study of the way living organisms are named, classified, treated, or used by different human cultures). It may also be about lay people’s classification of all other kinds of things (e.g., of celestial bodies, as in astrology, in ceramics, e.g., Kempton 1981; in colors, e.g., Davidoff 2015, in religious beliefs, e.g., Durkheim [1912]/2012; etc. etc.). In some domains, especially popular arts (painting, film literature, music etc.), it seems more difficult to distinguish lay and professional classifications because sociological studies of users have increasingly informed the scholarly communities [1].

Folk classification may also be termed “commonsense classification”, “intuitive classification”, “lay classification”, “indigenous classification”, “naïve classification” [2] (this term related to naïve domain theories (for an overview see Gelman and Noles 2011), such as “naïve biology”/”folk biology” [3], “naïve physics”/”folk physics” (e.g. Proffitt 1999), “naïve psychology”/”folk psychology” [4], “naïve sociology”/”folk sociology” (Hirschfeld 1999) etc. The term “primitive classification” was used by Durkheim and Mauss ([1903]/2010), but bear pejorative connotations and may misrecognize the value of folk classification. Folk classification has also been termed “quasi-scientific classification” and “vernacular classification” (e.g., by Wilkins and Ebach 2014, 81).

Folk classification as used here should not to be confused with the classification of peoples, for example, as “races”, cf. Shanklin (2008), although such a classification can be one kind of folk classification. Neither should folk classification be confused with → folksonomy or with individual variations in classification [5].

[top of entry]

2. Interdisciplinary research on folk classification

Hull (1999, 478) provides information about the disciplinary and interdisciplinary research in this field:

Several of the authors in this volume [Medin and Atran 1999] have produced bodies of work that are genuinely interdisciplinary, combining anthropology, evolutionary biology, cognitive psychology, history of science, and even philosophy.

The reason evolutionary biology is among the listed disciplines is, of course, that the book is about the domain folk biology. The general contributors to folk classification are the fields: anthropology and cognitive psychology with input from the specific domains, science studies and philosophy. In the introduction to the book, the psychologist and anthropologist Medin and Atran (1999, 2-8) provide a critical discussion and comparison of the role of cognitive psychology and anthropologists (ethnobiologists) in the research on folk biological. The critique of cognitive psychology says (3): “In short, it would not be much of a caricature to suggest that cognitive psychology does not quest for universality, but rather assumes it”. In addition, psychologists show little concern about reference (i.e., the objects that are classified, which demand input of domain knowledge). The criticism raised against anthropology is (5): “Again at the risk of caricature one might argue that ethnobiological observations often fall short of the minimum needed for scientific progress. In many cases ethnobiological facts and observations are presented in summary form without any clear indication of their source”.

The present article draws, as it will be clear, much on philosophy, which is seen as a very important contributor to this field. In the conclusion we shall consider how folk classifications have been considered in library and information science (LIS) with knowledge organization (KO).

[top of entry]

3. Relations between scholarly classification and folk classification

There are different views about the relations between scientific/scholarly classifications [6] on the one hand and folk classifications on the other hand. Wikipedia (2021) wrote: “Folk taxonomies are generated from social knowledge and are used in everyday speech. They are distinguished from scientific taxonomies that claim to be disembedded from social relations and thus objective and universal”. We have already seen in the last endnote that scientific classifications are perhaps only seldom based on consensus. Some researchers further deny that scientific classifications are objective and universal (see, e.g., Barnes, Bloor and Henry 1996). Bloor (1982) defends Durkheim and Mauss’ ([1903]/2010) view that: “the classification of things reproduces the classification of men”, that, for example the concept → “hierarchy” first existed in the social organization in societies, and later developed into an abstract concept used for classification in general. The same for other cognitive categories like space, time, number, and class. This view seems closely related to the claim that broader cultural issues in some way influences both folk classifications and scientific classifications.

One possible relation between scientific classification and folk classification is that folk classification is based on scientific classification (although in delayed and simplified ways). There have, for example, since about 1990 been a revolution in the scientific classification of birds (among many other kinds of things), cf. Fjeldså (2013), caused by, among other things, the use of DNA-analysis. This new classification is also used in new books about birds and field books used by amateur ornithologists. Sooner or later, it will probably be taught in schools, and it is not difficult to imagine that the main structure of this new (but still unfinished) classification will form the basis for folk classification in the future. Medin and Atran (1999, 11) wrote:

Although there has been little systematic study of the input conditions and processes by which scientific concepts are assimilated into lay thinking, there is hardly any doubt that science is pervasively involved in how people in our culture come to think about the biological world […] most of the general population is heavily exposed to scientific concepts in one form [or] another through schooling, nature programs on television, popular books, the press and so forth.

Another view is that folk classifications are rough systems for fields where no scholarly system was initially available, e.g., in oral cultures which do not know Western taxonomies. They tend to be accurate for items of interest to practical life, such as game animals, and much broader for those of less relevance, such as ant species and gradually to be replaced by scientific classifications. Medin and Atran (12) also wrote that although “ethnobiologists might well agree with psychologists about referring to lay biology in our culture as ‘naïve’” this is in relation to the relative sophistication of science as well as folkbiological knowledge in other cultures, on which is said (12):

The elaborate folkbiological inventories that ethnobiologists have shown time and again for many small-scale subsistence societies often match and occasionally even surpass in intricacy and accuracy the knowledge of field biologists working in the same locales as those societies.

Thus, some folk classifications are not primitive versions of scientific classifications but may match or perhaps even be more advanced than scientific classifications in certain respects. This has been reported, for example, about knowledge of potato varieties in the traditional agriculture of Liguria, Italy:

different local names can be referred to the same variety, but also, on the contrary, different varieties are called by the same name. To Giacumin from Vobbia, the same quarantina potatoes that are cultivated in Croce, Pentema, and Montoggio, villages just few kilometers away, are completely different varieties that he calls by different names, and I don't know how but he is able to tell them apart! (Angelini 2005)

This brings us to the third view about the relations between folk and scientific classifications: That folk classifications are not more primitive or temporary classifications to be replaced by scientific ones, but are alternative classifications (Gnoli 2011) fulfilling other tasks than the scientific ones (and sometimes even reveal scientific classifications as based on problematic assumptions [7]). Medin and Atran wrote (12):

If they [folk concepts and scientific concepts] are not really different in kind but only in degree of sophistication, then there may be no reason for holding onto the lay concept at all, except perhaps as an optional psychological convenience for navigating the everyday […].

If scientific classification and folk classification are not different in kind, we may be less interested in folk classification because it cannot teach us important new principles about classification. If, on the other hand, they represent different kinds of classification there are two options: Either folk concepts and classifications ought to be replaced by scientific concepts (Medin and Atran (13) provide an example of folk classification that should be discarded in line with the belief in witches or in race as a biological category) or the two kinds of classifications have different roles why folk classifications may be better fitted to the daily need of people compared to scientific classifications. The view that different cultures (or social groups, fields of knowledge or scientific paradigms) need different classifications is a pluralist and culture relative view, whereas the view that there is one dominant (or best) classification for all purposes is a monist view.

[top of entry]

4. Cultural relativist versus cultural universalist views

Atran (1999, 317) described the two positions in relation to folk classification:

Universalists highlight folk taxonomic principles that are only marginally influenced by people’s needs and uses to which taxonomies are put (Berlin 1992). Relativists emphasize those structures and contents of folk biological categories that are fashioned by cultural interest, experience, and use (Ellen 1993). Universalists grant that even within a culture there may be different special-purpose classifications (beneficial/noxious, domestic/wild, edible/inedible, etc.). However, there is only one cross-culturally universal kind of general-purpose taxonomy, which supports the widest possible range of inductions about living kinds. This distinction between special- and general-purpose folk biological classifications parallels the distinction in philosophy of science between artificial versus natural classification (Gilmour and Walters 1964 [1963]).

The debate between relativists and universalists is probably most developed and clear in research about color classification (often called “color categorization”, particularly by psychologists). As this encyclopedia includes an article → “Colour classification in natural languages” we shall not go deep into this domain here, but some general concepts will be used in order to discuss folk classification in general. Briscoe (2021, 456) mentions that human beings with normal, trichromatic vision have the capacity to discriminate approximately 2 million different shades of colour. Despite the fine-grained specificity with which we perceive colour, we tend to think and speak about colour in terms of a comparatively much small number of coarse-grained categories. English, for example, contains only 11 basic colour terms (BCT) — black, white, red, yellow, green, blue, brown, orange, pink, purple, and grey — while the unwritten languages of many non-industrialized societies contain as few as two or three BCTs. A problem, that has for a long time been central in cognitive science, anthropology and philosophy is whether this reduction of the millions of colors to a few used in our language and thinking is constrained by our universal physiological and psychological make-up, or if it is determined by our needs (as suggested by the well-known view that Eskimo has more words for snow compared, for example, to English, because they have a need to better differentiate kinds of snow) [8].

Briscoe (2021, 456-7; numbered listing emphasized) wrote:

The colour categorization debate has been traditionally framed as a conflict between ‘universalist’ and ‘relativist’ conceptions of the relation between language, thought, and perception […]. To simplify greatly,
Strong universalism maintains:
(1) that coarse-grained colour concepts corresponding to BCTs are unlearned, psychological universals that recur across maximally different cultures;
(2) that the psychological universality of these colour concepts is due to the perceptual salience of their best examples or ‘foci’; and, finally,
(3) that the representation of colour categories in language has no influence on the way colours are represented at the level of either thought or perception.
Strong linguistic relativism, in contrast, denies claim (1):
(1) basic colour concepts aren’t psychological universals, but vary instead with cultural and communicative needs.
(2) Hence, there are no cross-cultural patterns in colour categorization and colour-naming practices that demand scientific explanation, as assumed by claim (2).
(3) Strong linguistic relativists also deny claim (3), maintaining instead that colour terms are the primary vehicles of colour category representation and, strikingly, that an object’s apparent colour can vary as a function of the colour terms present in the perceiver’s language. In denying claim (3), strong linguistic relativism has an affinity with the writings of Benjamin Lee Whorf (1956). [9]

This debate is closely related to the problem of realism vs. idealism/constructivism. The universalist view is that groupings may stand out given only (a) the world’s objective attributes and (b) the human perceptual system, where (a) is the realist position, whereas (b) is a cognitivist, constructivist position. Both may be universalist in that they imply that either the world’s objective attributes or universal characteristics in our cognitive system dictates one correct classification. The culture relativist view, on the other hand, is related to social constructivism by claiming that in addition to the world and the human perceptual system, issues such as particular goals, needs, and interests may play a role in classifying (this view is therefore often called “the utilitarian view”). This is therefore about the role of the classifier as a social and cultural being and his or her knowledge, views, and needs. Malt (1995) suggested that both views may be partly correct (141):

objective facts of nature appear to dominate in cases when the world as filtered through the human perceptual system presents itself in discrete chunks. Such cases include biological categories at a middle level of abstraction. The […] human intellect in its role as classifier, becomes more important when nature and perception do not by themselves deliver the world prepackaged into obvious chunks. Such cases include biological categories at higher, and to some extent lower, levels of abstraction, and potentially many common categories in other domains.

Cognitivism is a position according to which folk-taxonomic structures are universal in a nontrivial sense due to universal, biological characteristics of our cognitive system. This view is called “convergence metaphysics” by Ludwig (2018) [10], who wrote (416-7):

[T]he prominence of convergence metaphysics cannot be understood independently of debates about universal cognitive structures that dominated the early days of the cognitive revolution. Universalism constituted a core theme in founding documents of volution, from Miller’s (1956) hypothesis of a general capacity of the human short-term memory to Chomsky’s (1965) universal grammar. Anthropologists who joined this young movement in the context of an “ethnoscientific” program often aimed for analogous insights about general rules and structures below the “surface” of cultural diversity. For example, Casagrande (1963:280) argued that anthropologists and linguists share “the task of uncovering the common pattern, or the universal design, that underlies the exuberant variety of the particular configurations that we call cultures and languages”. Convergence metaphysics would have been hardly possible without these universalistic ambitions that ethnobiologists shared with their peers in linguistics and psychology: instead of emphasizing the diversity of perspectives on the biological world, cognitive ethnobiology aimed at identifying underlying structures of convergence in classificatory systems.

Ludwig describes the rise and fall of cognitivism in folk classification and writes (423): “A pluralist metaphysics of ethnobiological classification provides resources to build bridges between methodological traditions by integrating concerns about locality and classification”. He also regrets that “debates about the metaphysics of ethnobiological classification have been largely in the doldrums since the 1990s”.

[top of entry]

5. Conclusion: The relevance of folk classification for the KO-community

There is a growing interest in the LIS and KO communities for developing services better suited for indigenous people. For example, Brian Deer (1945–2019) developed the Brian Deer Classification System (BDCS) (see Cherry and Mukunda 2015 and Doyle, Lawson and Dupont 2015). Littletree and Metoyer (2015) is about developing a thesaurus, while Duarte and Belarde-Lewis (2015) is about ontologies for indigenous people. There are also attempts to adjust existing knowledge existing systems to the needs of indigenous peoples, such as the Dewey Decimal Classification (Green 2015), the Library of Congress Subject Headings (Bone and Lougheed 2018) and → metadata standards (Montenegro 2019). There are also theoretical articles pointing out the problems of the traditional approaches to LIS and pointing towards the need for epistemological and critical studies (e.g., Littletree, Belarde-Lewis and Duarte 2020). Finally, an encyclopedia article about “Indigenous Librarianship” in LIS can be mentioned (Burns et al. 2009). It seems odd, however, that although the → user-based and cognitive approach have been influential in LIS and KO (see Hjørland 2013), this seems not to have been related to the field of folk classification as here presented. It is, for example, not visible in citations in the literature (it should be said, though, that the user-based and cognitive approach does not seem to have been much used regarding classification).

Considering the relation between folk classifications and scientific classifications, the main trend in LIS has been to follow Henry Bliss (1933), who argued (p. 37): “To make the [bibliographic] classification conform to the scientific and educational organization of knowledge is to make it the more practical”: Most bibliographic classification systems and → knowledge organization systems have followed scientific and scholarly classifications rather than folk classifications. Systems such as the Universal Decimal Classification (UDC) were in their heydays maintained by many international groups of subject specialists, and today’s front-end technology, the → ontologies, are clearly based on scientific and scholarly concepts. In relation to classification systems for public libraries the same applies, and the public libraries may be seen, like schooling, nature programs on television, popular books, and the press to contribute to disseminate the scientific world views (although library classifications often reflect outdated science, cf. Blake 2011, 469-70).

It is important to realize that research on folk classification addresses and illuminates fundamental problems in classification research which is important for LIS and KO, and which is in line with the increasing influence of pluralist philosophy. Andersen and Skouvig (2017) edited a book with the subtitle: “Caught between global structures and local meaning”, which seems closely related to what is discussed in this article.

If we assume that objects in the world can be described realistically, and that such descriptions are used for classifying the objects, it is possible, as the pluralists say, to be realist (objects do have the properties used for the classification) and at the same time to deny that there is only one correct way to classify things, as the monist view will have it. Dupré (1993) introduced the term “promiscuous realism” for this view. This is strongly associated with a utilitarian or pragmatic view, that different classifications are needed for different purposes and that a given classification cannot be evaluated without considering the goals it is meant to serve. Research on folk classification may also contribute clarifying such fundamental issues.

[top of entry]

6. Addendum June 2023

Wierzbicka (1996) discusses the distinction between scientific knowledge and everyday knowledge in the context of distinguishing between meaning and knowledge and between dictionaries and encyclopedias. She argues (p. 335-6) that meanings (e.g., the English word mouse) "do have boundaries, words can be rigorously defined, lexical fields with analogous semantic structures can be uncovered, and, on this basis, more or less reliable and accurate cognitive maps can be drawn". Although she (ibid., 337, footnote) wrote: "Whether or not 'folk knowledge' in general can always be distinguished, in a principled way, from 'scientific knowledge', is another matter, which need not concern us here at the moment, her assumption seems clearly to be that this is indeed the case. Before we consider her arguments, a comment on library classification should be made. As we wrote above (Section 5) a dominant ideal in bibliographic classification, as formulated by Bliss (1933), has been to make the classifications conform to the scientific organization of knowledge. This ideal has certainly mostly failed to be fulfilled, but that may be due to practical concerns. We (at least the author of this entry) have overlooked that Melvil Dewey actually warned against making library classifications "scientifically accurate", cf. Csiszar (2013, 444-5), which seems to reflect Szostak's (2022, 263) view: "Philosophers have long sought precision in argument, and much of the debate in concept theory concerns whether concepts can be defined precisely. KO is a practical field and can thus be more relaxed: If people have a broadly shared understanding of a concept we can usefully apply that concept in our efforts to guide people to the information they seek". Szostak (2011, 2247) suggests to analyze "complex concepts" into "basic concepts", that "can be understood in a similar way across disciplines and cultures". If we disregard different cultures (which certainly was not Wierzbicka's view), that one interpretation of Szostak (2011) is that there exists a broad "folk knowledge" (different from knowledge in specific disciplines) which can be used to construe "a truly universal classification". This raises the question whether there in bibliographic classification, from Dewey to Szostak has existed a mainly implicit and unexamined view corresponding to Wierzbicka's about basing meanings in dictionaries and classifications on everyday knowledge rather than on scientific knowledge? Wierzbicka (1996, 344) wrote:

The methodology for establishing the content (and also the form) of a given folk concept is a complex topic which cannot be discussed here at length [bibliographical references here omitted]. I will, however, adduce here examples of different kinds of evidence that can be used.

This is followed by a presentation, containing the following points.

  • Lexical evidence
  • Conventional metaphors
  • Proverbs and common sayings
  • Literature, in particular poetry
  • Ethnographic evidence of a non-linguistic type

Folk concepts cannot be established simply by putting direct questions to informants, because the kind of knowledge sought is tacit knowledge, although prolonged dialogue with a number of informants is also very useful, although more to verify than as a discovery tool. As already said, Wierzbicka believes that by using such methods, she is able to define "rigorously" the meaning in a natural language such as English. When she compares with how a concept (e.g., mouse) is defined in Encyclopedia Britannica. She describes a set of differences between the folk concept (as established by her own research) and the encyclopedia entry. Among other aspects, she wrote (343-4):

Reading the encyclopedia entry for mouse, one is struck by the mass of information which is clearly not part of the everyday concept, such as information on the geographical distribution of mice, on the length of the gestation period, on the maximum size of a litter, on metabolic disorders caused by overcrowding, and so on. On the other hand, a great deal of information which is essential to the everyday concept is missing. This includes, for example, on what mice might look like, on the way they move, on the sounds they make, on their special relationship with cats, on their 'psychological' characteristics, and so on. This is the way it should be: the encyclopedia is not aiming at capturing what is psychologically real and linguistically relevant (from the point of view of native speakers of English) [footnote here omitted]. But there should be another kind of compendium (a 'cultural dictionary') which would explicate the everyday concept of 'mice'.

An argument against Wierzbicka’s analysis is that she may underestimate the difference between different encyclopedias. Articles depends much on the individual authors’ knowledge and background and may also reflect cultural "bias". (See for example the English, German and French entries in Wikipedia: "Postcard", "Postkarte" and "Carte postale".) Authors with background in sociocultural anthropology may more likely write encyclopedia articles corresponding to Wierzbicka's "cultural dictionary", and such knowledge can be considered encyclopedic knowledge belonging to ethnobiology.

It seems fruitful to consider concepts, meanings and classifications to (ideally) reflect different needs, and the general language to reflect a mixture of these needs, with some more influential than others, and the common language only slowly to change according to new needs and scientific insights (such as the resent changing in bird classification, see Fjeldså 2013).

[top of entry]

Endnotes

1. About classification in popular music Venrooij and Schmutz (2015, 799) wrote: "On the one hand, classification systems arise out of processes of social distinction, whereby consumers use cultural objects to mark social boundaries. These 'ritual classifications' can thus be influenced by social structural factors at the societal level — such as stratification systems, elite cohesion, social and geographic mobility, etc. — that generate demand for cultural boundaries. On the other hand, classification systems are also influenced and mediated by 'classification processes' at the production side. DiMaggio (1987) identifies commercial classifications (the classifications used by commercial producers to market their products), administrative classifications (created and enforced by the state), and professional classifications (classifications driven by the incentives of artists to differentiate and mark boundaries). The study of classification systems thus needs to be attentive to the extent to which the categorical demands of consumers and the categories used by producers overlap, diverge, or mutually reinforce each other".
In his article about film genres, Bondebjerg (2001, 162) wrote: "In literary genre theory Todorov (Todorov [1970], 1975) made a distinction between theoretical and historical genres. Theoretical genres are defined in more general terms by criticism and theory and historical genres are defined as genres actively used and recognized by critics and readers". These two kinds of genres are by subsequent researchers used as a starting point for further developments in relation to film.

2. The term "naïve classification" has been used in another, very unfortunate, way by Beghtol (2003; 2004a), who claimed that classifications made by library and information professionals for information retrieval are "professional" classifications, whereas those made by other fields are "naïve". She wrote (Beghtol 2004a, 19): "Classifications for information retrieval can be called "professional" classifications and classifications in other fields can be called "naïve" classifications because they are developed by people who have no particular interest in classificatory issues". Hjørland and Nicolaisen (2004) wrote that it is wrong to consider LIS classification as more professional than domain classifications, on the contrary, LIS classifications depend very much on domain classifications. This provoked a reaction from Beghtol (2004b) and a rejoinder from Nicolaisen and Hjørland (2004). It can be added that also the association between LIS classification and information retrieval is problematic, as scientific and scholarly classifications also serve information retrieval.

3. Atran (1999, 317) defined "Folk biology is the cognitive study of how people classify and reason about the organic world". See also Medin and Atran (1999).

4. About folk psychology Baker (1999, 319) wrote: "[T]here are two different things that 'folk psychology' has come to mean and they are not always distinguished: (1) commonsense psychology that explains human behavior in terms of beliefs, desires, intentions, expectations, preferences, hopes, fears, and so on; (2) as an interpretation of such everyday explanations as part of folk theory, comprising a network of generalizations employing concepts like belief, desire, and so on. The second definition—suggested by Sellars (1963) and dubbed 'theory-theory' by Morton (1980)—is a philosophical account of the first".

5. Individual variations in classification have been studied in studies of "consistency of indexing" (see Lancaster 2003, 68-82). In astronomy, experimental psychology, and other fields of science, the term personal equation, in 19th- and early 20th-Century science, referred to the idea that every individual observer had a stable and inherent bias when it came to measurements and observations. This individual bias was measured and used to calculate more precise measures (see Hoffmann 2007).

6. It is important to realize that scientific/scholarly classifications not always are based on consensus. Broadfield (1946, p. 69-70) wrote: "Consensus is most likely to appear among the unenlightened, of whom it is characteristic to be unanimous on the truth of what is false. In intellectual matters agreement is rare, especially in live issue". Thus, it is perhaps truer to say that scientific classifications are never based on full consensus. (See, however, Cole 1992, Chapter 5: "Consensus in the Natural and Social Sciences", 102-36 in which it is shown that in relation to what is considered "core knowledge", as displayed by textbooks, the degree of consensus is much higher in the sciences compared to the social sciences.) The periodical system of chemistry and physics may be an exception from the claim that consensus never exists, but even here are disagreements about some specific elements, see, for example, Vernon (2020). Pluralism (which recognizes many equally correct views) is a growing position in the philosophy of science and in classification research. Concerning pluralism in classification research, Richards (2016) and Mai (2010) can be mentioned. Richards finished his book about biological classification in the chapter "The Essential Tension" and wrote (285) that the practice of biological classification will continue to be fraught with problems that arise from a fundamental psychological tendency in humans. May (2010, 627) wrote: "The purpose of this paper is to establish pluralism as the basis for bibliographic classification theory and practice". It should also be mentioned that in the history of, for example, biological classification, there have been much debate whether a given classification is "natural" of "artificial" (and about what these terms mean). Therefore, folk classification may not have one "correct" scientific classification to be compared to.

7. A good example of how "folk", in the form of gay activist groups, has changed a scientific classification is the case about removing homosexuality in the second edition of the → Diagnostic and Statistical Manual of Mental Disorders in 1973 (see Drescher 2015).

8. Martin (1986) is a critical review of the evidence for the view that Eskimo has more words for snow. The view lacks empirical support. Nonetheless, the cultural-relativist idea that utilitarian / pragmatic issues play a major role for how human classify is an important view.

9. The so-called Whorf hypothesis, also known as "Sapir-Whorf hypothesis" and "the linguistic relativity hypothesis" will be discussed in relation to color classification in the forthcoming IEKO article "Color classification in natural languages", in which it is also called the "Vico-Herder-Humboldt-Sapir-Whorf Hypothesis" to show its deeper historical origin. As the quote by Briscoe reveals, this hypothesis claims that different languages influence the way in which individuals perceive and thinks about objects, but the hypothesis is not closed, as Briscoe's article seems to indicate. Lucy (2015, 903) wrote: "Linguistic relativity stands in close relation to semiotic-level concerns with the general relation of language and thought, and to discourse-level concerns with how patterns of language use in cultural context can affect thought. Linguistic relativity is distinguished both from simple linguistic diversity and from strict linguistic determinism".

10. This article contains valuable comments from Eugene Anderson (423-4), Roy Ellen (424-6), Natalia Hanazaki (426-7), Eugene S. Hunn (427-8), L. M. Rival (428-9), Aung Si (429-30), Matthew H. Slater (430-1) and Daniel A. Weiskopf (431-2), as well as the author's reply to these comments (432-5).

[top of entry]

References

Andersen, Jack and Laura Skouvig (eds). 2017. The Organization of Knowledge: Caught Between Global Structures and Local Meaning. Bingley, United Kingdom: Emerald Publishing.

Angelini, Massimo. 2005. “Varietà tradizionali, prodotti locali ed esperienze”. L'Ecologist italiano 1, no. 3: 230-275.

Atran, Scott. 1999. “Folk biology”. In The MIT Encyclopedia of the Cognitive Sciences, eds. Robert Wilson and Frank Keil. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press, 317-9. Version (with different pagination: 316-7) available at: https://jeannicod.ccsd.cnrs.fr/ijn_00000267/document.

Baker, Lynne Rudder. 1999. “Folk Psychology». In The MIT Encyclopedia of the Cognitive Sciences, eds. Robert Wilson and Frank Keil. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press, 319-20.

Barnes, Barry, David Bloor and John Henry. 1996. Scientific Knowledge: A Sociological Analysis. Chicago: The University of Chicago Press.

Beghtol, Claire. 2003. “Classification for Information Retrieval and Classification for Knowledge Discovery: Relationships between “Professional” and “Naïve” Classifications”. Knowledge organization 30: 64-73.

Beghtol, Claire. 2004a. “Naïve Classification Systems and the Global Information Society”. Advances in Knowledge Organization 9: 19-22.

Beghtol, Claire. 2004b. Response to Hjørland and Nicolaisen. Knowledge Organization 31: 62-63.

Berlin, Brent. 1992. Ethnobiological Classification: Principles of Categorization of Plants and Animals in Traditional Societies. Princeton: Princeton University Press.

Blake, James. 2011. “Some Issues in the Classification of Zoology”. Knowledge Organization 38, no. 6: 463–72.

Bliss, Henry E. 1933. The Organization of Knowledge in Libraries and the Subject Approach to Books. New York: Henry Holt.

Bloor, David. 1982. “Durkheim and Mauss Revisited: Classification and the Sociology of Knowledge”. Studies in History and Philosophy of Science 13, no. 4:267—97.

Bondebjerg, Ib. 2001. “Film: Genres and Genre Theory.” In International Encyclopedia of the Social and Behavioral Sciences, eds. Neil J. Smelser and Paul B. Baltes. Amsterdam: Elsevier, vol. 9: 5640-6.

Bone, Christine and Brett Lougheed. 2018. “Library of Congress Subject Headings Related to Indigenous Peoples: Changing LCSH for Use in a Canadian Archival Context”. Cataloging & Classification Quarterly 56, no. 1 : 83-95. DOI: 10.1080/01639374.2017.1382641

Briscoe, Robert. 2021. “Colour Categorization and Categorical Perception”. In The Routledge Handbook of Philosophy of Colour, eds. Derek H. Brown and Fiona Macpherson. London: Routledge, 456-74.

Broadfield, Aubrey Alfred (Alan). 1946. The Philosophy of Classification. London: Grafton.

Burns, Kathleen, Ann Doyle, Gene Joseph and Allison Krebs. 2009. “Indigenous Librarianship”. In Encyclopedia of Library and Information Sciences, ed. Marcia J. Bates and Mary Niles Maack. 3rd ed. Boca Raton, FL: CRC Press, 2330-46.

Cherry, Alissa and Keshav Mukunda. 2015. “A Case Study in Indigenous Classification: Revisiting and Reviving the Brian Deer Scheme”. Cataloging & Classification Quarterly 53, nos. 5-6: 548-67. DOI: 10.1080/01639374.2015.1008717

Cole, Stephen. 1992. Making Science: Between Nature and Society. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.

Csiszar, Alex. 2013. "“Bibliography as Anthropometry: Dreaming Scientific Order at the fin de siècle". Library Trends 62, no. 2: 442–55. DOI: 10.1353/lib.2013.0041.

Davidoff, Jules. 2015. “Color Categorization across Cultures” . In Handbook of Color Psychology, edited by Andrew J. Elliot, Mark D. Fairchild and Anna Franklin. Cambridge UK: Cambridge University Press, 259–78.

Dedrick, Don. “Colour Classification in Natural Languages”. ISKO Encyclopedia of Knowledge Organization, eds. Birger Hjørland and Claudio Gnoli. https://www.isko.org/cyclo/colour.

DiMaggio, Paul. 1987. “Classification in Art”. American Sociological Review 52, no. 4: 440–55.

Doyle, Ann M., Kimberley Lawson and Sarah Dupont. 2015. “Indigenization of Knowledge Organization at the Xwi7xwa Library”. Journal of Library and Information Studies 13, no. 2: 107-34. doi:10.6182/jlis.2015.13(2).107

Drescher, Jack. 2015. “Out of DSM: Depathologizing Homosexuality”. Behavioral sciences (Basel) 5, no. 4: 565–75. doi: 10.3390/bs5040565

Dupré, John. 1993. The Disorder of Things: Metaphysical Foundations of the Disunity of Science. Cambridge MA: Harvard University Press.

Duarte, Marisa and Mirnda Belarde-Lewis. 2015. “Imagining: Creating Spaces for Indigenous Ontologies”. Cataloging & Classification Quarterly 53, nos. 5-6: 677-702. DOI: 10.1080/01639374.2015.1018396

Durkheim, Émile. 2012. The Elementary Forms of the Religious Life. Translated by Joseph Ward Swain. Newburyport: Dover Publications. (Original : Les formes e´le´mentaires de la vie religieuse: le système tote´mique en Australie. Paris, F. Alcan, 1912). Available in Project Gutenberg: https://www.gutenberg.org/ebooks/41360.

Durkheim, Émile and Marcel Mauss. 2010. Primitive Classification. Translated with and Introduction by Rodney Needham. New York: Routledge. (Translated from the French, De Quelques Formes Primitives de Classification, 1903.)

Ellen, Roy. 1993. The Cultural Relations of Classification. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

Fjeldså, Jon. 2013. “Avian Classification in Flux”. In Handbook of the Birds of the World. Special volume 17, eds. Josep del Hoyo, Andrew Elliott, Jordi Sargatal and David A. Christie. Barcelona: Lynx Edicions, 77-146 + references 493-501.

Gelman, Susan A. and Nicholaus S. Noles. 2011. “Domains and Naïve Theories”. WIREs Cognitive Science 2, no. 5: 490-502. https://doi.org/10.1002/wcs.124 [WIRE = Wiley interdisciplinary reviews].

Gilmour, John Scott, and Stuart Max Walters. 1963. “Philosophy and Classification”. In Vistas in Botany, vol. 4: Recent Researches in Plant Taxonomy, ed. William Bertram Turrill. Oxford: Pergamon Press, 1-22. https://doi.org/10.1016/B978-1-4831-9862-0.50006-8.

Gnoli, Claudio. 2011. “Animals belonging to the emperor: enabling viewpoint warrant in classification”. In Subject access: preparing for the future [Proceedings of IFLA Satellite Meeting, Florence, 20-21 August 2009], eds. Patrice Landry, Leda Bultrini, Edward T. O'Neill and Sandra K. Roe. Berlin: De Gruyter, 91-100.

Green, Rebecca. 2015. “Indigenous Peoples in the US, Sovereign Nations, and the DDC”. Knowledge Organization 42, no. 4: 211-21.

Hirschfeld, Lawrence A. 1999. “Naïve Sociology”. In The MIT Encyclopedia of the Cognitive Sciences, eds. Robert Wilson and Frank Keil. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press, 579-81.

Hjørland, Birger. 2013. “User-based and Cognitive Approaches to Knowledge Organization: A Theoretical Analysis of the Research Literature”. Knowledge Organization 40, no. 1: 11-27. Also available in ISKO Encyclopedia of Knowledge Organization, eds. Birger Hjørland and Claudio Gnoli, http://www.isko.org/cyclo/user_based.

Hjørland, Birger and Nicolaisen, Jeppe. 2004. “Scientific and Scholarly Classifications are not ‘Naïve’: A
Comment to Beghtol (2003)”. Knowledge Organization 31: 55-61.

Hoffmann, Christoph. 2007. “Constant Differences: Friedrich Wilhelm Bessel, the Concept of the Observer in Early Nineteenth-Century Practical Astronomy and the History of the Personal Equation”. British Journal for the History of Science 40, no. 146: 333-65. Part: 3. DOI: 10.1017/S0007087407009478.

Hull, David L. 1999. “Interdisciplinary Dissonance”. In Folk Biology, eds. Douglas L. Medin and Scott Atran. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press, 477-500.

Hunn, Eugene. 1975. “A Measure of the Degree of Correspondence of Folk to Scientific Biological Classification”. American Ethnologist 2, no. 2: 309-27.

Kempton, Willett. 1981. The Folk Classification of Ceramics: A Study of Cognitive Prototypes. New York: Academic Press.

Lancaster, Frederick Wilfrid. 2003. Indexing and Abstracting in Theory and Practice. 3. ed. London: Facet Publishing.

Littletree, Sandra and Cheryl Metoyer. 2015. “Knowledge Organization from an Indigenous Perspective: The Mashantucket Pequot Thesaurus of American Indian Terminology Project”. Cataloging & Classification Quarterly 53, nos. 5-6: 640-57. DOI: 10.1080/01639374.2015.1010113.

Littletree, Sandra, Miranda Belarde-Lewis and Marisa Duarte. 2020. “Centering Relationality: A Conceptual Model to Advance Indigenous Knowledge Organization Practices”. Knowledge Organization 47, no. 5: 410-26. DOI: 10.5771/0943-7444-2020-5-410.

Lucy, John A. 2015. “Sapir-Whorf Hypothesis”. In International Encyclopedia of the Social & Behavioral Sciences 2nd ed., ed. James D. Wright. Amsterdam: Elsevier, Volume 20: 903-6. http://dx.doi.org/10.1016/B978-0-08-097086-8.52017-0.

Ludwig, David. 2018. “Revamping the metaphysics of Ethnobiological classification”. Current Anthropology 59, no. 4: 415-38. DOI: 10.1086/69895.

Mai, Jens Erik. 2010. “Classification in a Social World: Bias and Trust”. Journal of Documentation 66, no. 5: 627-42.

Malt, Barbara C. 1995. “Category Coherence in Cross-Cultural Perspective”. Cognitive Psychology 29, no. 2: 85-148.

Martin, Laura. 1986. “Eskimo Words for Snow": A Case Study in the Genesis and Decay of an Anthropological Example”. American Anthropologist 88, no. 2: 418-23. http://languagelog.ldc.upenn.edu/myl/llog/LauraMartinEskimoSnowWords.pdf.

Medin, Douglas L. and Scott Atran, Eds. 1999. Folk Biology. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.

Montenegro, Maria. 2019. “Subverting the Universality of Metadata Standards: The TK Labels as a Tool to Promote Indigenous Data Sovereignty”. Journal of Documentation 75, no. 4: 731-49. DOI: 10.1108/JD-08-2018-0124.

Morton, Adam. 1980. Frames of Mind: Constraints on the Common-sense Conception of the Mental. Oxford, UK: Clarendon Press.

Nicolaisen, Jeppe and Hjørland, Birger. 2004. “A Rejoinder to Beghtol (2004)”. Knowledge Organization 31: 199-201.

Proffitt, Dennis. 1999. “Naïve Physics”. In The MIT Encyclopedia of the Cognitive Sciences, eds. Robert Wilson and Frank Keil. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press, 577-9.

Richards, Richard A. 2016. Biological Classification: A Philosophical Introduction. Cambridge, UK: The University of Cambridge Press.

Sellars, Wilfrid. 1963. “Empiricism and the Philosophy of Mind”. Reprinted in his Science, Perception, and Reality. London: Routledge and Kegan Paul.

Shanklin, Eugenia. 2008. “Folk Classification”. In Encyclopedia of Race and Racism, 3 volumes. Ed. John H Moore. Detroit: Macmillan Reference, vol 1: 478-9. Available as a free internet source at: https://ur.zlibcdn2.com/dl/610163/30fa53. Also available at Encyclopedia.com. Retrieved 2021-05-03 from: https://www.encyclopedia.com/social-sciences/ encyclopedias-almanacs-transcripts-and-maps/folk-classification

Todorov, Tzvetan. 1975. The Fantastic: A Structural Approach to a Literary Genre. Ithaca, N.Y.: Cornell University Press. (Translated by Richard Howard from Introduction à la littérature fantastique, Paris: E´ditions du Seuil, 1970).

Venrooij, Alex van and Vaughn Schmutz. 2015. “Classifications in Popular Music.” In International Encyclopedia of the Social and Behavioral Sciences, 2nd edition. Ed. James D. Wright. Amsterdam: Elsevier, vol. 3: 799-804.

Vernon, René E. 2020. “The Location and Composition of Group 3 of the Periodic Table”. Foundations of Chemistry. https://doi.org/10.1007/s10698-020-09384-2.

Wierzbicka, Anna. 1996. Semantics: Primes and Universals. Oxford, UK: Oxford University Press.

Wikipedia: The Free Encyclopedia. 2021. “Folk Taxonomy”. Retrieved 2021-05-03 from: https://en.wikipedia.org/wiki/Folk_taxonomy.

Wilkins, John S. and Malte C. Ebach. 2014. The Nature of Classification: Relationships and Kinds in the Natural Sciences. New York: Palgrave Macmillan.

[top of entry]

 

Visited Hit Counter by Digits times.


Version 1.0 published 2021-05-18
Version 2.0 published 2023-06-14: Section 6 added.

Article category: KO in different contexts and applications

This editorial article is not peer-reviewed and is not being published in the journal Knowledge Organization. How to cite it:
Hjørland, Birger and Claudio Gnoli. 2021. “Folk classification”. Preliminary editorial placeholder article. In ISKO Encyclopedia of Knowledge Organization, eds. B. Hjørland and C. Gnoli, .

©2021 ISKO. All rights reserved.